Abstracts

Creating the Kingdom of Ends: Abstracts of Essays

1. An Introduction to the Ethical, Political and Religious Thought of Kant

In this essay my aim is to provide a sympathetic account of Kant’s ethics in its historical setting. For Kant, the death of speculative metaphysics and the birth of the rights of humanity are not independent events: together they constitute the resolution of the enlightenment debate about the power of reason. Theoretical reason is unable to answer the questions of metaphysics, about God, Freedom, and Immortality. But this conclusion prepares the way for an extension in the power of practical reason. Practical reason directs that every human being be regarded as unconditionally valuable. This provides a rational foundation for morality and a moral foundation for liberal politics and religion.

2. Kant’s Analysis of Obligation: The Argument of Groundwork I

Most of the moves in the current debate about whether moral motivation is internal or external to moral judgment were anticipated in the eighteenth century British debate between the rationalists and the sentimentalists about obligation. The problem in both debates is how the thought of duty can at once motivate and bind every rational agent. By reconstructing Kant’s argument in the first section of the Groundwork, I show how Kant solves this problem. Only a law willed autonomously can motivate through the thought of its bindingness, and so only an action dictated by such a law can be obligatory.

3. Kant’s Formula of Universal Law

Kant asserts that the universalization of a maxim in violation of perfect duty is contradictory. I identify three interpretations of this claim in the literature: the universalized maxim (i) is logically contradictory; (ii) is contradictory only when considered as a teleological law; or (iii) is practically self-defeating. All are textually defensible but I argue that the third is philosophically superior. It harmonizes with Kant’s account of the analyticity of hypothetical imperatives and it enables the universalization test to handle more cases successfully.

4. Kant’s Formula of Humanity

In the Groundwork, Kant claims that, just as universalizability is the form of the moral principle, humanity is its matter. Drawing on Kant’s other works, I reconstruct Kant’s argument for the Formula of Humanity to determine why. Humanity is the capacity for free rational choice, fully realized in the good will, which brings value into the world and confers it on objects of rational choice. Using Kant’s examples, I then show how treating respecting this capacity amounts to treating humanity as an end-in-itself.

5. The Right to Lie: Kant on Dealing with Evil

Kant contends that one may not lie to a murderer who asks if his victim is concealed in one’s house; this suggests that moral rigorism leaves us powerless in the face of evil. I argue that such a lie can be shown to be permissible under the Formula of Universal Law, but not under the Formula of Humanity. Kantian rigorism does not stem from legalism, but from the high ideal of human relations implied by the Formual of Humanity. I resolve the problem by introducing Rawls’s distinction between ideal and non-Ideal theory into the Kantian system. Lying to the murder is permissible but morally regrettable because it is a violation of our ideal of human relationships.

6. Morality as Freedom

Kant argues that we are morally obligated because a free person would act morally, and a rational person must regard herself as free. Critics object that it is not obvious that a free person would act morally. Kant’s answer is that a free will must choose its own law, and the moral law, which directs the choice of a maxim with the form of a law, simply describes what a free will must do. Since we must act under the idea of freedom, moral action is rational for us, but in order to explain our interest in it, Kant invokes the noumenal/phenomenal distinction. If we regard ourselves as free, we must regard ourselves as noumena, and this places us among the forces that shape the phenomenal world. Critics object that if we are noumena and insofar as we are noumena we only do what is right, we cannot do voluntary evil actions. I argue that these objections spring from a failure to understand the radical nature of Kant’s separation of the explanatory and theoretical use of reason from its normative and practical use. Noumenal freedom is a postulate of practical reason, and the objections arise from employing it theoretically, which Kant’s philosophy forbids.

In the second part of the paper I explain the conception of moral virtue Kant’s theory of freedom requires. Kant thinks that because of our sensible nature, we always act for an end, so we must achieve freedom through the adoption of moral ends, which is virtue. One may object that action from moral ends does not make us free unless we adopt moral ends freely. I answer this by explaining why Kant thinks that freedom is something that we may attribute to ourselves as a result of progress in virtue rather than something we must have had already in order to become virtuous. If the moral law shows us how a free person would act, and if we can act on the moral law through virtue, then virtue makes us free.

7. Creating the Kingdom of Ends: Reciprocity and Responsibility in Personal Relations

Drawing on an account of friendship common to Aristotle and Kant, I argue that personal relations are characterized by an expectation of reciprocity that is only possible between those who hold one another responsible. Holding someone responsible may be understood either as having a belief about her or as taking up a practical attitude towards her. If it is the latter, as I argue, then we need practical reasons for holding people responsible. Kant’s ethical theory shows us what those reasons are. Holding ourselves and others responsible is a precondition for moral action, and so is what Kant calls a “postulate of practical reason.”

8. Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value

Kant holds that the good will is a source of value, in the sense that other things acquire their value from standing in an appropriate relation to it. I argue that Aristotle holds a similar view about contemplation, and that this explains his preference for the contemplative life. Kant and Aristotle differ about what the source of value is because they differ about which kind of activity, ethical or contemplative, gives meaning and purpose to the world.

9. Two Distinctions in Goodness

The distinction between final and instrumental goods is frequently and improperly conflated with the distinction between intrinsic (or unconditional) and extrinsic (or conditioned) goods. This conflation has serious consequences for value theory. In particular, it leads to the view that any extrinsically good thing whose goodness depends on its pleasantness is a mere means to pleasure. After considering these consequences I compare the views of two philosophers – Moore and Kant – who did not conflate the two distinctions, but who differ as to whether there are extrinsically good ends – that is, whether there are things which are final goods in virtue of the interest that people take in them or the value that people set on them. I challenge Moore’s view that final goodness is independent of interest and defend Kant’s view that rational choice can render a thing good.

10. The Reasons We Can Share: An Attack on the Distinction Between Agent-Relative and Agent-Neutral Values

The distinction between agent-relative (subjective) and agent-neutral (objective) reasons leaves an important option out: reasons may be intersubjective, or shared. I examine the examples that Nagel, uses in The View from Nowhere, to motivate the claim that some reasons are agent-relative: reasons springing from personal projects and deontological reasons. I argue that such reasons are better understood as intersubjective reasons. This is also a better way to understand agent-neutral reasons. The normativity of reasons does not spring from the claims made on us by either our personal projects or objective goods. It springs from the claims we make on one another.

11. Skepticism about Practical Reason

Hume and Williams argue that pure practical reason cannot be the foundation of morality because it cannot motivate. I show that all arguments for “motivational skepticism” must presuppose “content skepticism” – the view that pure practical reason has no action-guiding content. If pure practical reason is shown to have action-guiding content, Humean arguments cannot show that rational agents cannot be motivated by it. Skepticism about practical reason therefore cannot be based on motivational considerations alone.

12. Two Arguments Against Lying

Kant and Sidgwick take views at opposite extremes about whether we may tell paternalistic lies. I trace the extremism to their views about ethical concepts. Sidgwick thinks that fundamental ethical concepts must be capable of precise application. Common Sense morality says we may tell paternalistic lies to children but not to sane adults. Because the distinction between a child and an adult is imprecise, Sidgwick thinks this principle cannot be fundamental, and must be based on the principle of utility, which he thinks can always (in principle) be precisely applied, and which often mandates paternalistic lies to adults. Kant thinks that ethical concepts are ideals of reason, which cannot be applied to things in the empirical world precisely because the world is imperfect. We lie to children and the insane because they are not perfectly rational, but no one is perfectly rational. We must treat all persons with the respect due to rational agents, so the pressure of the theory is toward not lying to anyone. In this kind of ideal theory, decisions about where to draw the line must be made pragmatically, like the decision who counts as an adult in the law, and to some extent arbitrarily. But fear of this is not a good reason to abandon ethical ideals for utilitarianism.

13.Personal Identity and the Unity of Agency: A Kantian Response to Parfit

A person is both active and passive, both an agent and a subject of experiences. These are aspects of our nature, not parts, for agency may be regarded as a form of experience, and having experiences as something that we do. Parfit’s view that a person is not deeply unified over time depends on regarding the person as a subject of experiences, and agency as a form of experience. I argue that when persons are viewed as agents, and agency is not reduced to experience, we can see why persons are necessarily, though pragmatically, unified. I then put this conception of personal identity to work to show how moral conclusions that Parfit draws from his account may be blocked.